Search results

Filters

  • Journals
  • Authors
  • Keywords
  • Date
  • Type

Search results

Number of results: 40
items per page: 25 50 75
Sort by:
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

Przez twórców Poznańskiej Szkoły Metodologicznej rozumie się badaczy skupionych wokół Jerzego Kmity, Leszka Nowaka, Jerzego Topolskiego i Jana Sucha. Założenia badawcze kultywowane przez krąg poznańskich uczonych dotyczą warstwy ontologicznej oraz metodologicznej. Wśród twórców pewne istotne rozbieżności odnoszą się do zasady abstrakcji i w konsekwencji metod badawczych stosowanych w naukach społeczno-humanistycznych. Podczas gdy Leszek Nowak był przekonany, że główną metodą badań naukowych we wszystkich dziedzinach jest metoda idealizacji, to Jerzy Kmita sądził, iż nauki społeczno-humanistyczne głównie stosują nie metodę idealizacji, lecz metodę wyodrębniania w badanym przedmiocie układów relacyjnych za pomocą abstrakcji izolującej. Pojawienie się w naukach społecznych, a ściślej w polskiej humanistyce, zjawiska, które później miało uzyskać miano Poznańskiej Szkoły Metodologicznej, datuje się od 1970 roku. Przyjęty program badań metodologicznych w Polsce stanowił zapowiedź nowego stylu prowadzenia refleksji metodologicznej, stylu skrupulatnie zresztą później realizowanego. Najbardziej intensywny rozwój ośrodka poznańskiego przypada na lata siedemdziesiąte i dalsze. Do Poznańskiej Szkoły Metodologicznej należą jednak nie wszyscy metodologowie tego ośrodka. Ewolucja poglądów głównych twórców Szkoły świadczy, iż wiele idei ulegało daleko idącym przekształceniom. Modyfikowane, osiągały nieraz postać zaprzeczającą ich pierwotnej wersji.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Grażyna Musiał
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The article is devoted to a book by David lnving. Goebbels. Mózg Trzeciej Rzeszy (Goebbels, Brain of the Third Reich) published in the Polish translation in 1998.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Marcin Karas
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

In this paper I inquire whether Rawls’s ‘justice as fairness’ is a deontological concept. By arguing that it is, I place Rawls’s understanding of the deontological nature of his theory of justice in the context of the history of the notion of deontology. I argue that Rawls’s understanding of deontology is based on the choice of (inter)personal relations as the proper subject of ethics. To explicate this idea I draw on Rawls’s senior thesis A Brief Inquiry into the Meaning of Sin and Faith: An Interpretation based on the Concept of Community (1942).
Go to article

Bibliography

Adams R.M. (2009), The Theological Ethics of the Young Rawls and Its Background, w: J. Rawls, A Brief Inquiry into the Meaning of Sin and Faith: An Interpretation based on the Concept of Community with On My Religion, red. T. Nagel, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, s. 24–101.
Bentham J. (1983), Deontology, w: tenże, „Deontology” together with „A Table of Springs of Action” and „The Article on Utilitarianism”, red. A. Goldworth, Oxford: Clarendon Press, s. 117–281.
Broad C.D. (1930), Five Types of Ethical Theory, London: Routledge.
Cohen J., Nagel T. (2009), Introduction, w: J. Rawls, A Brief Inquiry into the Meaning of Sin and Faith: An Interpretation based on the Concept of Community with On My Religion, red. T. Nagel, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, s. 1–23.
Davis N.A. (2002), Deontologia współczesna, przeł. P. Łuków, w: P. Singer (red.), Przewodnik po etyce, Warszawa: Książka i Wiedza, s. 247–260.
Frankena W.K. (1973), Ethics, wyd. 2, New Jersey, Englewood Cliffs: Prentice‑Hall. Freeman S. (1994), Utilitarianism, Deontology, and the Priority of Right, „Philosophy & Public Affairs” 23 (4), s. 313–349.
Goldworth A. (1983), Editorial Introduction, w: J. Bentham, „Deontology” together with „A Table of Springs of Action” and „The Article on Utilitarianism”, red. A. Goldworth, Oxford: Clarendon Press, s. xi–xxxvi.
Kymlicka W. (1988), Rawls on Teleology and Deontology, „Philosophy & Public Affairs” 17 (3), s. 173–190.
Louden R.B. (1996), Toward a Genealogy of „Deontology”, „Journal of the History of Philosophy” 34 (4), s. 571–592.
Rawls J. (1998), Liberalizm polityczny, przeł. A. Romaniuk, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
Rawls J. (2000), Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy, red. B. Herman, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Rawls J. (2009a), A Brief Inquiry into the Meaning of Sin and Faith: An Interpretation based on the Concept of Community with On My Religion, red. T. Nagel, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Rawls J. (2009b), Teoria sprawiedliwości. Wydanie nowe, przeł. M. Panufnik, J. Pasek, A. Romaniuk, przekład przejrzał i uzupełnił S. Szymański, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
Reidy D.A. (2015), Deontological vs. Teleological Theories, w: J. Mandle, D.A. Reidy (red.), The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, s. 198–201.
Sandel M.J. (1982), Liberalism and Limits of Justice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Schneewind J.B. (2002), Jeremy Bentham. Introduction, w: tenże (red.), Moral Philosophy from Montaigne to Kant, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, s. 460–462.
Sidgwick H. (1907), The Methods of Ethics, wyd. 7, London: Macmillan and Company.
Timmermann J. (2014), Kantian ethics and utilitarianism, w: B. Eggleston, D. Miller (red.), The Cambridge Companion to Utilitarianism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, s. 239–257.
Timmermann J. (2015), What’s Wrong with „Deontology”, „Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society” 115 (1), s. 75–92.
Weithman P. (2016), Rawls, Political Liberalism and Reasonable Faith, New York: Cambridge University Press.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Krzysztof Kędziora
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Łódzki, Instytut Filozofii, ul. Lindleya 3/5, 90‑131 Łódź
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

During the second half of the past century the Catholic Christology suffered an anthioquian twist in order to overcome what the German theologian K. Rahner called «orthodox monophysitism» in his article about Chalcedon on the occasion of its 1500 th anniversary. For this, he proposed the recovery of a «strict chalcedonism» that opposed to the neochalcedonian interpretations of the 451’s Concillium. Maximus the Confessor has a decisive role in both Balthasar and Ratzinger’s Christology. With this, Ratzinger pretends to answer what he believed is the true danger in today’s theology. Contrary to J.A. Jungmann, K. Adam, K. Rahner, and F.X. Arnold’s thesis that denounced a factical monphysitism amongst the faithful, Ratzinger upholds that the reapparition of a new Nestorianism (and arianism) in today’s Christology is the true danger that must be fought against. In the first place, the article presents, synthetically, the post chalcedonian discussion, concentrating on the apparition of the theological trend of neochalcedonism and on Maximus the Confessor’s Christological contribution. From there on it approaches the neochalcedonian and maximillian interpretations that J. Ratzinger formulates in his sixth thesis of «Behold the Pierced One» and that will be later developed in the Gethsemani chapter of «Jesus of Nazareth».

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Raul Orozco Ruano
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The contribution of mercury and iodine in the particles of atmospheric aerosol and in the surface film of marine waters were estimated in the region of Admiralty Bay, King George Island, South Shetlands. Aerosols were collected with microscopic copper grids and on fibrous filters of microsorban type, and surface film with glassy slides. The obtained data are significant as natural background data.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Longina Felkier
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

In 2020, in Poland, a national commemoration of two eminent religious philosophers was celebrated: it was dedicated to the memory of Friar J.M. Bocheński O.P. and Pope St. John Paul II. In the paper, I recapitulate fundamental ideas of The Logic of Religion (1965) by the former author and sum up the key issues of the doctoral thesis The Doctrine of Faith in St. John of the Cross (1948) by the latter. I also mention St. John Henry Cardinal Newman’s Grammar of Ascent (1870), because in Polish translation this book is entitled A Logic of Faith. In order to compare those heterogeneous conceptions of religious faith I reach out to logical semiotics, and using its tools I try to find a symbolic meaning of religious speech that could be accepted equally by religious thinkers and by non‑believers. I propose to understand religious speech as having not only literal sense, and not only a metaphysical meaning, but also, as I claim, the power to activate values that guide human behavior. I hope this is a conciliatory proposition because it places semiotics on a neutral footing among religious dogmas. In this perspective, mysticism can be described as a pragmatic aspect of language that emerges when a user refers to a transcendent reality.
Go to article

Bibliography

1. Alighieri D. (2004), Biesiada, przeł. M. Bartkowiak‑Lerch, Kęty: Antyk.
2. Bocheński J.M. (1988), Między logiką a wiarą. Z Józefem M. Bocheńskim rozmawia Jan Parys, Montricher: Les Editions Noir Sur Blanc.
3. Bocheński J.M. (1990), Logika religii, przeł. S. Magala, Warszawa: Instytut Wydawniczy Pax.
4. Bocheński J.M. (1993), Sens życia, Kraków: Philed.
5. Bocheński J.M. (1994), Sto zabobonów, Kraków: Philed.
6. Gronczewska A. (2009), Szyfrant, który sprawił cud, „Dziennik Łódzki”, https:// dzienniklodzki.pl/szyfrant-ktory-sprawil-cud/ar/185093
7. Jan od Krzyża św. (1975), Dzieła, t. I–II, przeł. o. Bernard od Matki Bożej, wyd. III, Kraków: Wydawnictwo oo. Karmelitów Bosych.
8. Newman J.H. (1989), Logika wiary, przeł. P. Boharczyk, Warszawa: Instytut Wydawniczy Pax.
9. Poe E.A. (1986), Złoty żuk, w: tenże, Opowiadania, t. 1, przeł. S. Wyrzykowski, Warszawa: Czytelnik.
10. Pseudo‑Dionizy Areopagita (1997), Teologia symboliczna, w: tenże, Pisma teologiczne, przeł. M. Dzielska, Kraków: Znak.
11. Wojtyła K. (1959), Ocena możliwości zbudowania etyki chrześcijańskiej przy założeniach systemu Maksa Schelera, Lublin: Towarzystwo Naukowe KUL.
12. Wojtyła K. (1990), Zagadnienie wiary w dziełach św. Jana od Krzyża, przeł. o. Leonard od Męki Pańskiej OCD, Kraków: Wydawnictwo oo. Karmelitów Bosych.
13. Zieliński T. (1999), Chrześcijaństwo antyczne, Religie Świata Antycznego, T. VI, Toruń: Wydawnictwo Adam Marszałek.


Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Łukasz Kowalik
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Warszawski, Wydział Filozofii, Redakcja „Przeglądu Filozoficznego”, ul. Krakowskie Przedmieście 3, 00-927 Warszawa
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

Bertrand Russell formulated neutral monism by default, unguided by any strong idea of a uniform, monistic world. Apparently he worked under the urge to liberate philosophy from the quarrel between physicalists and idealists. But he did not succeed in defusing the controversy, instead he fanned it with his fresh ideas. He argued that matter was indestructible, that some mental regularities occurred independently of our will, and that they unfold as if guided by natural laws. He claimed that some conscious states were to be interpreted as objective events despite the fact that they were accessible only privately. But the concurrence between physical and mental facts indicated a similarity between the principles that guided them, or pointed to their singular common nature. He did not undertake to defend his unitary theory vigorously and did not claim it was indisputable. Possibly he hoped to find an additional support for his theory some day and this paper responds to this unspoken request.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Jacek Hołówka
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Warszawski, Wydział Filozofii, ul. Krakowskie Przedmieście 3, 00-927 Warszawa
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The aim of this paper is to highlight the relationship between normative theory and social ontology through an analysis of John Rawls’s concept of ‘well‑ordered society’. By expressing the ontological assumptions underlying Rawls’s theory, it is possible to better understand the role of practices and institutions in A Theory of Justice and to counter some of the criticisms levelled against Rawls’s institutionalism. The proposed interpretation of Rawls’s theory may be recognized as a contribution to the interactionist approach in the field of social ontology.
Go to article

Bibliography

Berkey B. (2016), Against Rawlsian Institutionalism about Justice, „Social Theory and Practice” 42 (4), s. 706–732.
Ciszewski W. (2020), Rozum i demokracja. Wprowadzenie do koncepcji rozumu publicznego Johna Rawlsa, Kraków: Wydawnictwo Uniwersytetu Jagiellońskiego.
Cohen G.A. (1997), Where the Action Is: On the Site of Distributive Justice, „Philosophy & Public Affairs” 26 (1), s. 3–30.
Diver N. (2004), Institutions and Social Justice [nieopublikowana rozprawa doktorska], University of Pennsylvania.
Frega R. (2018), The Social Ontology of Democracy, „Journal of Social Ontology” 4 (2), s. 157–185.
Kwarciński T. (2006), Możliwości czy dobra pierwotne? Dyskusja Amartyi Sena z Johnem Rawlsem na temat właściwej przestrzeni sprawiedliwości, „Roczniki Filozoficzne” 54 (1), s. 81–106.
Mandle J. (2009), Rawls’s „A Theory of Justice”: An Introduction, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mandle J., Reidy D.A. (red.) (2014), The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Murphy L.B. (1998), Institutions and the Demands of Justice, „Philosophy & Public Affairs” 27 (4), s. 251–291.
Nozick R. (1974), Anarchy, State and Utopia, New York: Basic Books.
Pettit P. (2005), Rawls’s Political Ontology, „Politics, Philosophy & Economics” 4 (2), s. 157–174.
Pettit P. (2006), Rawls’s Peoples, w: R. Martin, D.A. Reidy (red.), Rawls’s Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia, Hoboken, NJ: Wiley‑Blackwell, s. 38–55.
Rawls A. (2009), An Essay on Two Conceptions of Social Order, „Journal of Classical Sociology” 9 (4), s. 500–520.
Rawls J. (1955), Two Concepts of Rules, „The Philosophical Review” 64 (1), s. 3–32.
Rawls J. (2009), Teoria sprawiedliwości, przeł. M. Panufnik, J. Pasek, A. Romaniuk, S. Szymański, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
Sen A. (2009), The Idea of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Wojciech Graboń
1
ORCID: ORCID
Marcin Woźny
2 3
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Warszawski, Szkoła Doktorska Nauk Humanistycznych, ul. Krakowskie Przedmieście 26/28, 00‑927 Warszawa
  2. Uniwersytet Warszawski, Wydział Filozofii, ul. Krakowskie Przedmieście 3, 00‑927 Warszawa
  3. Uniwersytet Warszawski, Wydział Prawa i Administracji, ul. Krakowskie Przedmieście 26/28, 00‑927 Warszawa
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The paper analyses and develops John Rawls’s defence of his theory of justice against the conservative objection that egalitarian conceptions of social justice are an expression of envy. The defence involves the following claims: (1) The content of the difference principle does not match an essential property of envy. (2) The parties in the original position are not motivated by envy. (3) None of the conditions imposed on the original position arise from envy. Next, it is argued that there are reasons to suppose that the parties in the original position would choose a more egalitarian principle of distributive justice than the difference principle. These reasons are grounded in the claim that self respect is the most important primary good and in the fact that the level of economic inequalities is negatively correlated with self respect among the least advantaged members of society. It is shown that even though the content of the more egalitarian principle matches the essential property of envy, the conservative objection remains unjustified.
Go to article

Bibliography

Crocker J., Blanton H. (1999), Social Inequality and Self‑Esteem: The Moderating Effects of Social Comparison, Legitimacy, and Contingencies of Self‑Esteem, w: T.R. Tyler, R.M. Kramer, O.P. John (red.), The Psychology of the Social Self, Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, s. 171–191.
Krauss M.W., Park J.W. (2014), The Undervalued Self: Social Class and Self-‑Evaluation, „Frontiers of Psychology” 5, s. 1–9.
Nozick R. (2010), Anarchia, państwo, utopia, przeł. P. Maciejko, M. Szczubiałka, Warszawa: Fundacja Aletheia.
Rawls J. (2009), Teoria sprawiedliwości. Wydanie nowe, przeł. M. Panufnik, J. Pasek, A. Romaniuk, przekład przejrzał i uzupełnił S. Szymański, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
Schoeck H. (1969), Envy: A Theory of Social Behavior, London: Secker and Warburg.
Tesser A. (1988), Toward a Self‑Evaluation Maintenance Model of Social Behavior, „Advances in Experimental Social Psychology” 21, s. 181–227.
Wilkinson R., Pickett K. (2011), The Spirit Level: Why Greater Equality Makes Societies Stronger, New York: Bloomsbury Publishing.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Adrian Kuźniar
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The idea that everyone should accept the terms of a contract, provided that others do so, is the core normative idea of John Rawls’s doctrine of social justice, presented in his major books: A Theory of Justice and Political Liberalism. In the present paper I argue that the principle of reciprocity makes it possible for Rawls to intertwine coherently two competing thought streams in the liberal tradition – the first one focusing on economic equality and the second one rooted in liberty. The idea of reciprocity adopted with the intention of satisfying the ideal of reasonableness in a well‑ordered society is the foundation of a genuine acceptance of the political conception of justice and of the civic ties and civic friendship. However, the historical and cultural analysis supports the conclusion that the Rawls’s project is buttressed by multigenerational experience of the discipline and ethos of the free market economy, which has not been openly endorsed by Rawls. Without support from such experience social solidarity within ethically neutral institutions would be hard to achieve unless it is expressed in terms of communitarian, patriotic or religious values.
Go to article

Bibliography

Barry B. (1989), Theories of Justice, t. I, Berkeley: University of California Press.
Dańkowski D. (2013), Rawls on Religion in Public Debate, Kraków: WAM.
Dańkowski D. (2021), Odpowiedzialny patriotyzm a walka o uznanie, w: M. Bogunia-Borowska (red.), Kultura (nie)odpowiedzialności, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
Dreben B. (2003), On Rawls and Political Liberalism, w: S. Freeman (red.), The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Freeman S. (2003), Introduction: John Rawls – An Overview, w: tenże (red.), The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gutmann A. (2003), Rawls on the Relationship between Liberalism and Democracy, w: S. Freeman (red.), The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Habermas J. (2015), Teoria działania komunikacyjnego, przeł. A. Kaniowski, t. I, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
James A. (2014), Political Constructivism, w: J. Mandle, D. Reidy (red.), A Companion to Rawls, Blackwell Companions to Philosophy, Malden, MA: Wiley‑Blackwell.
Kelly E. (2014), Inequality, Difference, and Prospects for Democracy, w: J. Mandle, D. Reidy (red.), A Companion to Rawls, Blackwell Companions to Philosophy, Malden, MA: Wiley‑Blackwell.
Lesiński B., Rozwadowski W. (1985), Historia prawa, wyd. IV, Warszawa – Poznań: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe.
Lister A. (2011), Justice as Fairness and Reciprocity, „Analyse & Kritik” 1, Stuttgart: Lucius & Lucius, s. 93–112.
Nagel T. (2003), Rawls and Liberalism, w: S. Freeman (red.), The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Nozick R. (1999), Anarchia, państwo, utopia, przeł. P. Maciejko, M. Szczubiałka, Warszawa: Fundacja Aletheia.
Nussbaum M. (2007), Frontiers of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Olszewski H., Zmierczak M. (1994), Historia doktryn politycznych i prawnych, Poznań: Ars Boni.
Ossowska M. (1985), Moralność mieszczańska, Wrocław: Zakład Narodowy im. Ossolińskich.
Rawls J. (1996), Political Liberalism. Reply to Habermas, w: tenże, Political Liberalism, New York: Columbia University Press.
Rawls J. (1998), Liberalizm polityczny, przeł. A. Romaniuk, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
Rawls J. (2001a), Collected Papers, red. S. Freeman, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Rawls J. (2001b), Prawo ludów. O idei publicznego rozumu raz jeszcze, w: tenże, Prawo ludów, przeł. M. Kozłowski, Warszawa: Fundacja Aletheia.
Rawls J. (2003), Justice as Fairness. A Restatement, red. E. Kelly, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Rawls J. (2009), Teoria sprawiedliwości, przeł. M. Panufnik, J. Pasek, A. Romaniuk, S. Szymański, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
Ricoeur P. (2018), O sobie samym jako innym, przeł. B. Chełstowski, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
Scanlon T.M. (2003), Rawls on Justification, w: S. Freeman (red.), The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Velasquez M. (1998), Business Ethics. Concepts and Cases, Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice‑Hall.
Weber M. (2010), Etyka protestancka a duch kapitalizmu, przeł. B. Baran, P. Miziński, Warszawa: Fundacja Aletheia.
Weithman P. (2013), Why Political Liberalism? On John Rawls’s Political Turn, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Williams H.L. (2014), The Law of Peoples, w: J. Mandle, D. Reidy (red.), A Companion to Rawls, Blackwell Companions to Philosophy, Malden, MA: Wiley‑Blackwell.
Ziembiński Z. (1992), O pojmowaniu sprawiedliwości, Lublin: Daimonion.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Dariusz Dańkowski SJ
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Akademia Ignatianum w Krakowie, ul. Kopernika 26, 31‑501 Kraków
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The first part of the article presents historical origins of Moses Mendelssohn’s Jerusalem (1783). It discusses Mendelssohn’s polemics with Johann Caspar Lavater, Christian Wilhelm Dohm and August Cranz which paved the way for the publication of the book. The second part treats Mendelssohn’s notion of Judaism as it is expressed in Jerusalem. Here the article argues for a fundamentally orthodox attitude of Mendelssohn toward Judaism, which prevented him from creating (a fact sometimes lamented by commentators) a far‑reaching ‘synthesis’ between the Jewish religion and the Enlightenment.
Go to article

Bibliography

1. Altman A. (1973), Moses Mendelssohn. A Biographical Study, Philadelphia: The Jewish Publication Society of America.
2. Altman A. (1981), Essays in Jewish Intellectual History, Hanover – New Hampshire – London: Brandies University Press.
3. Altman A. (1983), Commentary, w: M. Mendelssohn, Jerusalem or on Religious Power and Judaism, przeł. A. Arkush, Hanover – London: University Press of New England, s. 141–241.
4. Bałaban M. (1925), Historia i literatura żydowska, t. III, Lwów – Warszawa – Kraków: Zakład Narodowy im. Ossolińskich.
5. Cranz A. (1781), Ueber den Missbrauch der geistlichen Macht, oder, Der weltlichen Herrschaft in Glaubenssachen durch Beyspiele aus dem jetzigen Jahrhundert ins Licht gesetzt, Berlin.
6. Cranz A. (1782), Das Forschen nach Licht und Recht in einem Schreiben an herrn Moses Mendelssohn auf Veranlassung seiner merkwürdigen Vorrede zu Menasseh Ben Israel, Berlin: Friedrich Maurer.
7. Feiner S. (2002), The Jewish Enlightenment, przeł. Ch. Naor, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
8. Feiner S. (2010), Moses Mendelssohn: Sage of Modernity, przeł. A. Berris, New Heaven – London: Yale University Press.
9. Fichte J.G. (1793), Beitrag zur Berichtigung der Urteile des Publikums über die französische Revolution. Erster Teil. Zur Beurteilung ihrer Rechtmäßigkeit, Danzig: Ferdinand Troschel.
10. Gottlieb M. (2011a), Introduction, w: M. Mendelssohn, Writings on Judaism, Christianity, and the Bible, red. M. Gottlieb, przeł. C. Bowman, E. Sacks, A. Arkush, Waltham, MA: Brandeis University Press.
11. Gottlieb M. (2011b), Faith and Freedom: Moses Mendelssohn’s Theological‑Political Thought, New York: Oxford University Press.
12. Graetz M. (1996), The Jewish Enlightenment, w: M.A. Meyer (red.), German‑Jewish History in Modern Times, Vol. l: Tradition and Enlightenment: 1600–1780, przeł. W. Templer, New York: Columbia University Press.
13. Heine H. (2018), Z dziejów religii i filozofii w Niemczech, w: tenże, O Niemczech i o sobie. Wybór pism, przeł. T. Zatorski, Warszawa: Fundacja Augusta hr. Cieszkowskiego.
14. Herder J.G. (2013), Gott. Einige Gespräche über Spinoza’s System nebst Shaftesbury’s Naturhymnus, Berlin: Holzinger.
15. Hess J.M. (2000), Johann David Michaelis and the Colonial Imaginary: Orientalism and the Emergence of Racial Antisemitism in Eighteenth‑Century Germany, „Jewish Social Studies” 6 (2), s. 56–101.
16. Katz J. (1980), From Prejudice to Destruction. Anti‑Semitism 1730–1933, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
17. Kozyra (2020), Kant on the Jews and their Religion, „Diametros” 17 (65), s. 32–55.
18. Kuehn M. (2001), Kant. A Biography, New York: Cambridge University Press.
19. Lavater J.C. (1770), Johann Caspar Lavaters Zueignungsschrift der Bonnetischen Philosophischen Untersuchung der Beweise für das Christenthum an Herrn Moses Mendelssohn in Berlin, Zürich.
20. Lavater J.C. (1843), Antwort an den herrn Moses Mendelssohn, w: M. Mendelssohn, Gesammelte Schriften. Dritter Band, red. G.B. Mendelssohn, Leipzig: F.U. Brodhaus, s. 51–79.
21. Leibowitz Y. (1994), Gespräche über Gott und die Welt, red. M. Shashar, przeł. M. Schmidt, Frankfurt am Main – Leipzig: Insel Verlag.
22. Lessing G.E. (1959), Die Erziehung des Menschengeschlechts, w: tenże, Gesammelte Werke, t. I, red. W. Stammler, München: C. Hanser, s. 1010–1035.
23. Levinas E. (1991a), Przypadek Spinozy, w: tenże, T rudna wolność. Eseje o judaizmie, przeł. A. Kuryś, Gdynia: Atext, s. 111–115.
24. Levinas E. (1991b), Myśl żydowska dzisiaj, w: tenże, Trudna wolność. Eseje o judaizmie, przeł. A. Kuryś, Gdynia: Atext, s. 167–175.
25. Łastik S. (1961), Z dziejów Oświecenia żydowskiego, Warszawa: Państwowy Instytut Wydawniczy.
26. Majmon S. (2007), Autobiografia, t. 2, przeł. L. Belmont, Warszawa: Midrasz.
27. Margalit A., Halbertal M. (1994), Liberalism and the Right to Culture, „Social Research” 61 (3), s. 491–510.
28. Mendelssohn M. (1782), Vorrede, w: Menasseh Ben Israel, Rettung der Juden, przeł. M. Herz, Berlin – Stettin: Friedrich Nicolai.
29. Mendelssohn M. (1843a), Schreiben an der herrn Diaconus Lavater zu Zürich von Moses Mendelssohn, w: tenże, Gesammelte Schriften. Dritter Band, red. G.B. Mendelssohn, Leipzig: F.U. Brodhaus, s. 37–51.
30. Mendelssohn M. (1843b), Betrachrungen über Bonnet’s Palingenesie, w: tenże, Gesammelte Schriften. Dritter Band, red. G.B. Mendelssohn, Leipzig: F.U. Brodhaus, s. 135–177.
31. Mendelssohn M. (1844), Moses Mendelssohns Briefe an Herz Homberg, w: tenże, Gesammelte Schriften. Fünfter Band, red. G.B. Mendelssohn, Leipzig: F.U. Brodhaus, s. 651–687.
32. Mendelssohn M. (2005), Jerusalem oder über religiöse Macht und Judentum, red. M. Albrecht, Hamburg: Felix Meiner.
33. Mendelssohn M. (2011a), Letter to Rabbi Jacob Emden, 26 October 1773, w: tenże, Writings on Judaism, Christianity, and the Bible, red. M. Gottlieb, przeł. C. Bowman, E. Sacks, A. Arkush, Waltham, MA: Brandeis University Press, s. 32–35.
34. Mendelssohn M. (2011b), From Light for the Path, w: tenże, Writings on Judaism, Christianity, and the Bible, red. M. Gottlieb, przeł. C. Bowman, E. Sacks, A. Arkush, Waltham, MA: Brandeis University Press, s. 189–202.
35. Mendelssohn M. (2013), W kwestii: co znaczy oświecać, w: tenże, Wybór pism filozoficznych, przeł. R. Kuliniak, T. Małyszek, Wrocław: Atut.
36. Mendelssohn M. (2015), Do przyjaciół Lessinga, przeł. A. Chmielewski, red. T. Małyszek, R. Kuliniak, Wrocław: Atut.
37. Meyer M.A. (1967), The Origins of the Modern Jew. Jewish Identity and European Culture in Germany 1749–1824, Detroit: Wayne State University Press.
38. Meyer M.A. (1995), Response to Modernity. A History of the Reform Movement in Judaism, Detroit: Wayne State University Press.
39. Moritz K.P. (2015), Moses Mendelssohn do przyjaciół Lessinga. Dodatek do korespondencji Pana Jacobiego na temat nauki Spinozy, przeł. T. Małyszek, R. Kuliniak, w: M. Mendelssohn, Do przyjaciół Lessinga, przeł. A. Chmielewski, red. T. Małyszek, R. Kuliniak, Wrocław: Atut.
40. Pilarczyk K., Dublański R. (2016), Moses Mendelssohn a judaizm i kultura żydowska, „Studia Gdańskie” 38, s. 75–87.
41. Popkin R.H. (2002), Spinoza’s Excommunication, w: H.M. Ravven, L.E. Goodman (red.), Jewish Themes in Spinoza’s Philosophy, Albany: State University of New York Press, s. 263–281.
42. Rosenstock B. (2010), Philosophy and the Jewish Question. Mendelssohn, Rosenzweig, and Beyond, New York: Fordham University Press.
43. Schulte Ch. (2002), Die jüdische Aufklärung. Philosophie, Religion, Geschichte, München: C.H. Beck.
44. Sorkin D. (2008), The Religious Enlightenment. Protestants, Jews, and Catholics From London to Vienna, Princeton – Oxford: Princeton University Press.
45. Stern E. (2017), Enlightenment Conceptions of Judaism and Law, w: Ch. Hayes (red.), The Cambridge Companion to Judaism and Law, New York: Cambridge University Press, s. 215–232.
46. Wahle H. (1993), Wspólne dziedzictwo: judaizm i chrześcijaństwo w kontekście dziejów zbawienia, przeł. Z. Kowalska, Tarnów: Biblos.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Wojciech Kozyra
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The article discusses Rawls’s idea of the original position. I present two arguments in support of the claim that it is impossible to meet the necessary conditions (proposed by Rawls) for recreating the reasoning that presumably is performed in the original position. I claim therefore that the idea of the original position cannot fulfil its function of justifying the principles of justice. As the solution to the problem I propose a modified version of the original position argument, which can be labeled ‘a slightly lifted veil of ignorance’.
Go to article

Bibliography

Bostrom N. (2003), Are you living in a computer simulation?, „Philosophical Quarterly” 53, s. 243–255.
Chyrowicz B. (2021), Widok stąd. Dlaczego działamy tak, a nie inaczej?, Kraków: Znak.
Dworkin R. (1977), Justice as Rights, w: tenże, Taking Rights Seriously, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, s. 150–183.
Freeman S. (2007), Rawls, London – New York: Routledge.
Graham P. (2007), Rawls, Oxford: Oneworld.
Hare R.M. (1973), Rawls’s Theory of Justice II, „The Philosophical Quarterly” 23, s. 241–252.
Hinton T. (2015), Introduction, w: tenże (red.), The Original Position, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, s. 1–17.
Kukathas Ch., Pettit P. (1990), Rawls:„A Theory of Justice” and its Critics, Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Levin M. (1978), The Problem of Knowledge in the Original Position, „Auslegung: A Journal of Philosophy” 5 (3), s. 147–159.
Mulhall A., Swift A. (1996), Liberals and Communitarians, wyd. II, Oxford – Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Publishers.
Rawls J. (1999), Theory of Justice. Revised Edition, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Rawls J. (2001a), Outline of a Decision Procedure for Ethics, w: tenże, Collected Papers, red. S. Freeman, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, s. 1–19.
Rawls J. (2001b), The Independence of Moral Theory, w: tenże, Collected Papers, red. S. Freeman, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, s. 286–302.
Rawls J. (2001c), Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical, w: tenże, Collected Papers, red. S. Freeman, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, s. 388–414.
Rawls J. (2005), Political Liberalism. Expanded Edition, New York: Columbia University Press.
Sandel M. (2004), Republika proceduralna i nieuwarunkowana jaźń, przeł. P. Rymarczyk, w: P. Śpiewak (red.), Komunitarianie. Wybór tekstów, Warszawa: Fundacja Aletheia, s. 71–90.
Sandel M. (2009), Liberalizm a granice sprawiedliwości, przeł. A. Grobler, Warszawa: Wydawnictwa Akademickie i Profesjonalne.
Singer P., de Lazari‑Radek K. (2013), Konsekwencjalizm a tajemnica: obrona ezoterycznej moralności, „Analiza i Egzystencja” 22, s. 5–32.
Szutta A. (2010), Cnota rozsądności, w: N. Szutta (red.), Współczesna etyka cnót: możliwości i ograniczenia, Warszawa: Semper, s. 195–204.
Szutta A. (2013), Metoda refleksyjnej równowagi. Część I: prezentacja metody, „Diametros” 37, s. 129–149.
Szutta A. (2015), W poszukiwaniu zasad sprawiedliwości, „Filozofuj!” 5, s. 29–30.
Szutta A. (2018), Intuicje moralne. O poznaniu dobra i zła, Lublin: Academicon.
Śpiewak P. (red.) (2004), Komunitarianie. Wybór tekstów, Warszawa: Fundacja Aletheia.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Artur Szutta
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Gdański, ul. J. Bażyńskiego 4, 80‑309 Gdańsk
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

John Rawls claims that self‑respect is arguably the most important of social primary goods. It has two aspects: the sense of self‑worth and confidence in one’s abilities. Both attitudes presuppose formation and completion of a reasonable life plan. Realization of a life plan is a stepping stone to personal achievement and happiness. Self‑respect implies acceptance of two rules of justice. Those rules presuppose an equal distribution of the social prerequisites for the growth of self‑respect. Self‑respect supports the sense of justice as well as political and social stability. A well‑ordered society makes it possible for everyone to achieve self‑respect through realization of an ambitious life plan, in accordance with Aristotelian conception of virtue. Virtue is also a prerequisite of happiness. In a poorly‑ordered society achievement of happiness is thwarted by socio‑economic inequality and artificial restrictions on selection of the life plans.
Go to article

Bibliography

Alexy R. (1987), John Rawls’ Theorie der Grundfreiheiten, w: W. Hinsch (red.), Zur Idee des politischen Liberalismus. John Rawls in der Diskussion, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Chmielewski A. (2001), Społeczeństwo otwarte czy wspólnota?, Wrocław: Oficyna Wydawnicza Arboretum.
Fukuyama F. (2004), Koniec człowieka, przeł. B. Pietrzyk, Kraków: Znak.
Gawkowska A. (2004), Biorąc wspólnotę poważnie. Komunitariańskie krytyki liberalizmu, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo IFiS PAN.
Kukathas Ch., Pettit Ph. (1998), Rawls: „A Theory of Justice” and its Critics, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Leschke M. (1995), Die Beiträge von John Rawls und James Buchanan zum Aufbau einer demokratischen Grundordnung, w: I. Pies, M. Leschke (red.), John Rawls’ politischer Liberalismus, Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck).
Prostak R. (2004), Rzecz o sprawiedliwości. Komunitarystyczna krytyka współczesnego liberalizmu amerykańskiego, Kraków: Wydawnictwo Uniwersytetu Jagiellońskie-go.
Rau Z. (2008), Zapomniana wolność. W poszukiwaniu historycznych podstaw liberalizmu, Warszawa: Scholar.
Rawls J. (1994), Teoria sprawiedliwości, przeł. M. Panufnik, J. Pasek, A. Romaniuk, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
Rawls J. (1998), Liberalizm polityczny, przeł. A. Romaniuk, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
Zink J.R. (2011), Reconsidering the Role of Self‑Respect in Rawls’s „A Theory of Justice”, „The Journal of Politics” 73 (2), s. 331–344.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Barbara Grabowska
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Mikołaja Kopernika w Toruniu, Instytut Filozofii, ul. Fosa Staromiejska 1a, 87‑100 Toruń
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The aim of this article is to offer an in‑depth analysis of the quality of the basic act of phenomenological cognition. By juxtaposing arguments by Jan Patočka and Paul Ricoeur, the author concludes that neither negation (as Patočka claims) nor affirmation (as Ricoeur believes) but only fundamental questioning contributes to the development of fundamental phenomenological experience. From this perspective, the ‘thing of thinking’ is neither non‑Being (nothingness), nor Being, but the attitude of inquisitiveness. Philosophical acts of affirmation and negation, the correlates of which are Being and non‑Being, are responses to the basic experience of questioning. Persistence in the belief that questions have a leading role in philosophy strengthens the position of written communication as the proper medium of expression in philosophical inquiry.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Daniel Roland Sobota
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Polska Akademia Nauk, Instytut Filozofii i Socjologii, ul. Nowy Świat 72, 00-330 Warszawa
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The aim of the article is to examine the specific properties of language actions in terms of their moral evaluation. The author starts from the question whether responsibility for words has the same meaning as responsibility for a physical action. In her analysis, the author deliberates whether in both cases the same rules and criteria are applicable. Referring to the classical theory of speech acts proposed by John L. Austin, who introduced a fundamental division into constative and performative utterances and went on to distinguish illocutionary effects from perlocutionary consequences of speech acts, the author investigates how far a subject is responsible for the words he uses.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Karolina Rozmarynowska
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The study focuses on the relationship between the ethics of reading and the narrator’s unreliability in the novel by Kazuo Ishiguro The Remains of the Day. Drawing on James Phelan’s research, the authoress states that unreliability that can be attributed to the narrator of Ishiguro’s novel can be classified as either an error of being in the wrong or withholding some information consciously. Consequently, six types of unreliability can be distinguished: misreporting, misinterpreting, misevaluating, underreporting, underinterpreting, underevaluating. Employing these categories, the authoress analyses a literary text and lists different types of unreliability which are characteristic of Stevens, the main character and the narrator in Ishiguro’s novel.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Anna Głąb
ORCID: ORCID
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

In the article the Author presents the typology of alternative history and un its light he characterises the historical writings of Jerzy Łojek, in particular his approach towards history of November Uprising, 1830-1831.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Krzysztof Brzechczyn
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The paper attempts to place John Rawls’s social theory in an ontological frame of ideas. Józef M. Bocheński’s theory of systems was chosen to describe social reality without prejudging its role in the adequate theory. By adopting this approach the author presents several issues one by one: the characteristics of political philosophy and its relation to the ontology of social reality, Bocheński’s systems theory, the analysis of the industrial enterprise as a model example of a heterogeneous, dynamic and organic system, and Rawls’s structure of society. All this is done in terms of systems theory. The resulting outcome provides, among other things, a formal definition of Rawls’s basic social structure expressed in the language of systems theory, and it supports the thesis that the synthetic entity responsible for social functioning, such as the state, is correlated with the principles of justice as proposed by Rawls.
Go to article

Bibliography

Bertalanffy L. (1984), Ogólna teoria systemów. Podstawy, rozwój, zastosowania, przeł. E. Woydyłło‑Woźniak, Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe.
Bocheński J.M. (1986), The Concept of the Free Society, „The Monist” 69 (2), s. 207– 215.
Bocheński J.M. (1993), Przyczynek do filozofii przedsiębiorstwa przemysłowego, przeł. J. Garewicz, w: J.M. Bocheński, Logika i filozofia, red. J. Parys, Biblioteka Współczesnych Filozofów, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
Bunge M. (1979), Treatise on Basic Philosophy, vol. 4: Ontology II: A World of Systems, Dordrecht – Boston – London: D. Reidel Publishing Company.
Ingarden R. (1972), Książeczka o człowieku, Kraków: Wydawnictwo Literackie.
Ingarden R. (1974), Wstęp do fenomenologii Husserla, przeł. A. Półtawski, Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe.
Ingarden R. (1987), Spór o istnienie świata, t. I, t. II, cz. 1 i 2, wyd. III, Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe.
Kaczmarek J. (2008), Indywidua. Idee. Pojęcia. Badania z zakresu ontologii sformalizowanej, Łódź: Wydawnictwo Uniwersytetu Łódzkiego.
Kaczmarek J. (2016), Atom ontologiczny: atom substancji, „Przegląd Filozoficzny – Nowa Seria” 4 (100), s. 109–124.
Rawls J. (1971), A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Rawls J. (1993), Political Liberalism, New York: Columbia University Press.
Rawls J. (1999), The Law of Peoples, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Rawls J. (2001), Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, red. E. Kelly, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Stróżewski W. (2003), Ontologia, Kraków: Znak – Aureus.
Wenar L. (2021), John Rawls, w: E.N. Zalta (red.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Summer 2021 Edition, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/rawls/.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Janusz Kaczmarek
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Łódzki, Instytut Filozofii, ul. Lindleya 3/5, 90-131 Łódź
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The article expands and modifi es the contexts in which literary onomastics currently operates. This strictly interdisciplinary field of research, primarily originating from linguistics, has sought out the contexts that triggered non-obvious meanings of names readable in the artistic work from the outset. The references were varied – stylistics, textology, philosophy, structural poetics. All of them significantly enriched onomastic analyses, leaving some fundamental sense of insufficiency at the same time. That is the reason why we propose the project of the connection between literary onomastics and — now extremely extensive — theoretical thought. The article is not the end of this discussion, but rather an exploratory study and the beginning of scientific research. Consequently, there is no one ordering and chronological concept with a clear conclusion, but the main aim is to show the analysis of the claims relevant for further research. Therefore, several concepts of theoreticians interested in proper names in literature were discussed (far from a common phenomenon in this case). From the research projects analyzed, including among others: U. Eco, J.F. Lyotard, P. de Man, there emerges a clear conviction of the need to end the search for a referential, texted name. In this place it refers, on the one hand, to itself, establishing its own unreal meaning (image-forming, phonic, intertextual); on the other, it concerns the author’s system of naming (and beyond), which is also an epistemological concept. The starting point of these diagnoses was the thoroughly interpreted self-analysis of artistic works made by Marcel Proust; for further analysis, the thesis of Walter Benn Michaels was also employed, which brings interest in proper names from literature to the domain of artistic experiences. The conducted analysis (designing future literary onomastic research) leads to the fi nal conclusion that the proper name indicates the essence itself, the arche of our existence.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Magdalena Graf
Paweł Graf
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The issue of rationality and the term itself appear in the works of John Rawls, for instance in his famous volume A Theory of Justice. At the same time, in another of his books, Political Liberalism, we can find not only the correlated terms ‘rational’, but also the term ‘reasonable’. In that volume Rawls enlightens their meaning. In this article, the author analyses the terms mentioned more closely and reflects on their use in various contexts. The explanatory hypothesis adopted by the author is that the use of these two terms, not just one of them, may enrich our conceptual network and increase the possibilities of analysing the sphere of human action. The aim of the analyses is to confirm this hypothesis and to extract the specific sense of the term ‘reasonable’, and of its use, especially in Rawls’s Political Liberalism.
Go to article

Bibliography

Arystoteles (1982), Etyka nikomachejska, przeł. D. Gromska, wyd. 2, Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe.
Audi R. (2001), The Architecture of Reason. The Structure and Substance of Rationality, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Audi R. (red.) (1998), Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Golden J.L., Pilotta J.J. (red.) (1986), Practical Reasoning in Human Affairs, Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.
Honderich T. (1999), Encyklopedia filozofii, t. II, przeł. J. Łoziński, Poznań: Zysk i S‑ka.
Höffe O. (1995), Immanuel Kant, przeł. A.M. Kaniowski, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
Jolivet R. (1966), Vocabulaire de la Philosophie, Lyon: Emmanuel Vitte.
Kalinowski G. (1978), Logique et méthodologie juridique. Réflexions sur la rationalité formelle et non formelle en droit, „Archive de Philosophie de Droit” 23, s. 59–68.
Kant I. (1953), Uzasadnienie metafizyki moralności, przeł. M. Wartenberg, przekład przejrzał R. Ingarden, Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe.
Kant I. (1993), Religia w granicach samego rozumu, przeł. A. Bobko, Kraków: Znak.
Kleszcz R. (1998), O racjonalności. Studium epistemologiczno‑metodologiczne, Łódź: Wydawnictwo Uniwersytetu Łódzkiego.
Kleszcz R. (2005), Teoria argumentacji, filozofia, logika. Uwagi o teorii Chaima Perelmana, „Forum Artis Rhetoricae” 1–2, s. 22–35.
Kleszcz R. (2007), O rozumie i wartościach, Łódź: Wydawnictwo WSHE w Łodzi.
Lalande A. (red.) (1960), Vocabulaire technique et critique de la philosophie, Paris: PUF.
Laughlin S.K., Hughes D.T. (1986), The Rational and the Reasonable: Dialectic or Parallel Systems?, w: J.L. Golden, J.J. Pilotta (red.), Practical Reasoning in Human Affairs, Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.
Perelman Ch. (1979a), Logique juridique. Nouvelle rhétorique, Paris: Dalloz.
Perelman Ch. (1979b), The Rational and the Reasonable, w: T.F. Geraets (red.), Rationality Today, Ottawa: The Ottawa University Press, s. 213–224.
Perelman Ch., Olbrechts‑Tyteca L. (1983), Traité de l’argumentation. La nouvelle rhétorique, wyd. 4, Bruxelles: Editions de l’Université de Bruxelles.
Podsiad A. (2000), Słownik terminów i pojęć filozoficznych, Warszawa: Instytut Wydawniczy Pax.
Rawls J. (1951), Outline of a Decision Procedure for Ethics, „The Philosophical Review” 60, s. 177–197.
Rawls J. (1994), Teoria sprawiedliwości [1971], przeł. M. Panufnik, J. Pasek, A. Romaniuk, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
Rawls J. (1998), Liberalizm polityczny [1993], przeł. A. Romaniuk, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
Rescher N. (1954), Reasonableness in ethics, „Philosophical Studies” 5, s. 58–62.
Sibley W.M. (1953), The Rational versus the Reasonable, „The Philosophical Review” LXII (4), s. 554–560.
Simpson J.A., Weiner E.S.C. (red.) (1991), The Oxford English Dictionary [cyt. jako: OED], Oxford: Clarendon Press, Vol. XIII.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Ryszard Kleszcz
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Łódzki, Instytut Filozofii, ul. Lindleya 3/5, 90-131 Łódź
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

Although John Rawls’s theory is an extensive project of the state structure which also discusses the functions of various democratic institutions, the reader tends naturally to look for something more, namely his opinions about human nature and the psychological underpinnings that ultimately determine men’s and women’s responsibilities in a democratic community. The clues offered by A Theory of Justice are disappointingly scarce, as they tend to blur the distinction between the descriptive and the normative aspects of the problem. Rawls’s analysis of such categories as moral sensitivity, or human motives, or social obligations do not take into account the natural limitations that typically accompany the demands formulated by the just state. Or, to put the same complaint differently, Rawls’s opinions about human nature sound unduly optimistic, if compared, for instance, with Kant’s moral theory to which he makes frequent references.
Go to article

Bibliography

Feinberg J. (1975), Rawls and Intuitionism, w: N. Daniels (red.), Reading Rawls: Critical Studies on Rawls’ „A Theory of Justice”, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Frankfurt H.G. (1997), Wolność woli i pojęcie osoby, przeł. J. Nowotniak, w: J. Hołówka (red.), Filozofia moralności. Postanowienie i odpowiedzialność moralna, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Spacja – Fundacja Aletheia.
Hobbes Th. (2005), Lewiatan, przeł. Cz. Znamierowski, Warszawa: Fundacja Aletheia.
Kant I. (2005a), Antropologia w ujęciu pragmatycznym, przeł. E. Drzazgowska, P. Sosnowska, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo IFiS PAN.
Kant I. (2005b), Metafizyka moralności, przeł. E. Nowak, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
MacIntyre A. (2007), Czyja sprawiedliwość? Jaka racjonalność?, red. A. Chmielewski, Warszawa: Wydawnictwa Akademickie i Profesjonalne.
Nagel Th. (1975), Rawls on Justice, w: N. Daniels (red.), Reading Rawls: Critical Studies on Rawls’ „A Theory of Justice”, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Rawls J. (1988), The Priority of Right and Ideas of the Good, „Philosophy & Public Affairs” 17 (4).
Rawls J. (1994), Teoria sprawiedliwości, przeł. M. Panufnik, J. Pasek, A. Romaniuk, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
Rawls J. (2010), Wykłady z historii filozofii polityki, przeł. S. Szymański, Warszawa: Wydawnictwa Akademickie i Profesjonalne.
Rousseau J.J. (1966), Umowa społeczna, przeł. A. Peretiatkowicz, Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Joanna Górnicka-Kalinowska
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. prof. em., Uniwersytet Warszawski, Wydział Filozofii, ul. Krakowskie Przedmieście 3, 00‑927 Warszawa
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

My current considerations concern the way in which the category of animals is present in contemporary philosophy, especially if it occurs in the context of moral philosophy and the theory of cognition and mind. These are, I suppose, the areas of inquiry inspiring wide interest, even if we focus on the narrow question of the place of animals in the domains of morality, cognition, and consciousness. Although John Rawls himself approaches these issues with caution, and his interest in these types of problems is marginal, they deserve some philosophical attention. There is a close relationship between the belief that non‑personal living entities such as animals are capable of feeling pain and pleasure on the one hand, and the human sensitivity or social sentience, on the other. We should face the question of what kind of society we want to live in: effective or sensitive. Ethical utilitarianism is in favor of an effective society. It may seem that there is no place for social sensitivity in it, and consequently that public interest is postulated in its place instead. However, I believe that an effective society is more sensitive to the harm done to or the plight suffered by non‑personal subjects than a sensitive society, if the latter is understood as Rawls frames it. Thus, we come to a specific paradox – which I shall refer to as the blunted sentience paradox – that the utilitarian, efficient society criticized by Rawls is in fact more morally sensitive than the egalitarian society he postulates. The paradox of the blunted sentience has its source in Rawls’s egalitarianism, for this egalitarianism is offered only to the chosen. It does not extend to those members of society who extend their care to those creatures whom Rawls denies subjectivity, but whose unhappiness constitutes an important factor in the social life of humanity. I propose to look at the fate of animals in modern society, and if we do so, we will notice some flaws in Rawls’s theory of justice that can perhaps be amended by espousing some aspects of emotivism. This proposed approach avoids what I have called the blunted sentience paradox.
Go to article

Bibliography

Andrews K. (2020), The Animal Mind: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Animal Cognition, New York: Routledge.
Berkey B. (2014), Review of Robert Garner „A Theory of Justice for Animals: Animal Rights in a Nonideal World”, „Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews”, https://ndpr. nd.edu/reviews/a‑theory‑of‑justice‑for‑animals‑animal‑rights‑in‑a‑nonideal‑world/
DeGrazia D. (2002), Animal Rights: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Garner R. (2013), A Theory of Justice for Animals: Animal Rights in a Nonideal World, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hobson‑West P., Davies A. (2018), Societal Sentience: Constructions of the Public in Animal Research Policy and Practice, „Science, Technology, and Human Values” 43 (4), s. 671–693.
Marris C. (2015), The Construction of Imaginaries of the Public as a Threat to Synthetic Biology, „Science as Culture” 24 (1), s. 83–98.
Pisula W. (2003), Psychologia zachowań eksploracyjnych zwierząt, Gdańsk: Gdańskie Wydawnictwo Psychologiczne.
Rawls J. (2006), Teoria sprawiedliwości, przeł. M. Panufnik, J. Pasek, A. Romaniuk, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
Rowlands M. (2013), Can animals be moral?, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sumpter D.J.T. (2006), The Principles of Collective Animal Behaviour, „Philosophical Transactions: Biological Sciences” 361 (1465), s. 5–22.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Adriana Schetz
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Szczeciński, Instytut Filozofii i Kognitywistyki, ul. Krakowska 71–79, 71-017 Szczecin
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

John Rawls’s theory is blamed by political realism for adopting the position of political moralism, i.e. for subordinating politics to morality and understanding political phi-losophy as applied ethics. This article addresses these charges. It addresses a number of issues: How does Rawls understand politics? Does he understand it at all? Does the theory of liberalism realistically describe democracies? What is its normative character? In what sense is it a ‘realist utopia’? By posing these questions this paper analyzes the self‑limiting, restrained character of political liberalism, which is a result of the realistic recognition of the fact of pluralism of reasonable doctrines in modern liberal societies. It is pointed out, however, that liberalism is not conceived as a self‑limiting political liberalism of Rawls, but as a ‘comprehensive doctrine’ that constitutes a unified ideological foundation for modern ‘liberal democracy’. The self‑limitation of liberalism cannot be sustained in this way, however, as is evidenced by the fact that Rawls’s theory attempting to separate the political sphere from the ‘background culture’ has clearly failed.
Go to article

Bibliography

Arendt H. (2005), Polityka jako obietnica, red. J. Kohn, przeł. W. Madej, M. Godyń, Warszawa: Prószyński i S‑ka.
Deneen P.J. (2018), Why Liberalism Failed, Yale: Yale University Press.
Geuss R. (2008), Philosophy and Real Politics, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Gledhill J. (2012), Rawls and Realism, „Social Theory and Practice” 38 (1), s. 55– 82.
Goodhart D. (2017), The Road to Somewhere: The Populist Revolt and the Future of Politics, London: Hurst.
Habermas J. (2019), Auch eine Geschichte der Philosophie, Berlin: Suhrkamp.
Krasnodębski Z. (2011), Cztery sposoby unicestwienia polityki, w: tenże, Większego cudu nie będzie, Kraków: Ośrodek Myśli Politycznej, s. 135–147.
Legutko R. (2016), The Demon in Democracy: Totalitarian Temptations in Free Societies, New York: Encounter Books.
Marchart O. (2010), Die politische Differenz. Zum Denken des Politischen bei Nancy, Lefort, Badiou, Laclau und Agamben, Berlin: Suhrkamp.
Platon (1987), Listy, przeł. M. Maykowska, Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe.
Rawls J. (1998), Liberalizm polityczny, przeł. A. Romaniuk, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
Rawls J. (2001), Prawo ludów, przeł. M. Kozłowski, Warszawa: Fundacja Aletheia.
Sandel M. (2014), Przeciwko udoskonalaniu człowieka. Etyka w czasach inżynierii genetycznej, przeł. O. Siara, Warszawa: Kurhaus.
Wildstein B. (2020), Bunt i afirmacja. Esej o naszych czasach, Warszawa: Państwowy Instytut Wydawniczy.
Williams B. (2006), In the Beginning was the Deed: Realism and Moralism in Political Argument, red. G. Hawthorn, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Zdzisław Krasnodębski
1 2
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Akademia Ignatianum w Krakowie, Instytut Nauk o Polityce i Administracji, ul. Kopernika 26, 31‑501 Kraków
  2. Universität Bremen, FB 8 Sozialwissenschaften, Bibliothekstraße 1, 28359 Bremen, Niemcy
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

Looking at something is considered a fundamental act of awareness. What constitutes its embodied manifestation – the gaze – can be realized as a specific axiological variant of the value of evil. The article is devoted to this particular, closed-in-the‑gaze manifestation of the value of evil in the literary work. The point of reference is identified in two famous epic works: Doctor Faustus by Thomas Mann (1947) and The Kindly Ones by Jonathan Littell (2006). The evil gaze identifies the main characters of either novel, Adrian Leverkühn and Maximilian Aue. Whether the artistic structuring of the evil gaze is presented in the novels with the same means, or perhaps with the use of different tools of literary transmission of axiological content, is the issue lying at the center of considerations. In fact, it is not the only issue, as it is part of a broader reflection on the so-called restraining of values in a literary work in general. (Translated from Polish by Katarzyna Rogalska‑Chodecka)
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Beata Garlej
1

  1. Uniwersytet Kardynała Stefana Wyszyńskiego w Warszawie, Instytut Literaturoznawstwa, ul. Dewajtis 5, 01-815 Warszawa

This page uses 'cookies'. Learn more