Search results

Filters

  • Journals
  • Keywords
  • Date

Search results

Number of results: 3
items per page: 25 50 75
Sort by:
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The paper tries to defend the thesis that it is impossible to decide upon moral issues without any references to the ontology of the world we live in. An illustrative example of the main argumentation line is the choice made by Cypher—a second plan character in the movie Matrix. Cypher decides to betray human rebels fighting against machines for freedom and, as a reward, accepts affluent life in the virtual reality. His choice seems to be superficially reprehensible because of the abandonment of the real world and authentic life. However, one can argue that the dichotomy between the real and virtual world is seeming. By choosing the virtual reality Cypher decided to act in a world which, like the real world, makes it possible to be a moral subject and enables authentic experience. The difference between both the worlds lies in the type of determination limiting any conscious subject. Cypher prefers to live in a world determined by the algorithm of Matrix more than in a world where his behaviour is determined by genes and other biological factors.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Jacek Gurczyński
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

Antirealism is often regarded by philosophers as a model example of contemporary anti‑Cartesianism, chiefly because of the argumentation by Hilary Putnam presented in his Brains in a Vat and deeply rooted in antirealist semantics. But if we look closer, relations between Cartesianism and antirealism cannot be reduced to an opposition but are much more complex. Like Cartesianism, antirealism also attaches great significance to methodology universal for all philosophy, although antirealist ‘philosophy of thought’, contrary to its Cartesian counterpart, is antipsychological and boils down to Wittgensteinian philosophy that interprets language as something inherently public. But Dummettian antirealism contains also a Fregean concept of systematic theory of meaning, which should provide clear view of language rules and give us an ability to correct our imperfect language practice. For Wittgenstein and Putnam, who view this practice as the essence of language, this kind of attempt to correct language from outside is unacceptable. In this matter, Michael Dummett seems to be rather in harmony with the Cartesian ideal of thought as pure and distinct, and with the program of detached rationality. This impression is strengthened by his demand to adopt a ‘full‑blooded’ theory of meaning. Moreover, as it has been noted by Timothy Williamson, antirealism demands luminosity of meaning, which makes you wonder if it is not, like Cartesianism, one more case of epistemological foundationalism. These problems of antirealism seem to suggest strong internal tensions arising from an attempt, not entirely successful, to unify the thought of later Wittgenstein with more traditional rationalisms of Descartes and Frege.
Go to article

Bibliography

1. Ambrus V. (1999), Is Putnam’s Causal Theory of Meaning Compatible with Internal Realism?, „Journal for General Philosophy of Science” 30, s. 1–16.
2. Candlish S., Wrisley G. (2019), Private Language, w: E.N. Zalta (red.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall Edition), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/ fall2019/entries/private‑language/
3. Czerniawski K. (2010), Argument teoriomodelowy trzydzieści lat później, „Filozofia Nauki” 71 (3), s. 19–41.
4. Czerniawski K. (2014), Trzy wersje epistemicznej teorii prawdy: Dummett, Putnam, Wright, Warszawa: Ośrodek Badań Filozoficznych.
5. Diamond C. (1991), The Realistic Spirit: Wittgenstein, Philosophy, and the Mind, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
6. Dummett M. (1973), Frege: Philosophy of Language, New York: Harper & Row.
7. Dummett M. (1978), Truth and Other Enigmas, London: Duckworth.
8. Dummett M. (1987a), Reply to John McDowell, w: B. Taylor (red.), Michael Dummett: Contributions to Philosophy, Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, s. 253–268.
9. Dummett M. (1987b), Reply to Neil Tennant, w: B. Taylor (red.), Michael Dummett: Contributions to Philosophy, Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, s. 235–252.
10. Dummett M. (1993a), The Seas of Language, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
11. Dummett M. (1993b), Origins of Analytical Philosophy, London: Duckworth.
12. Dummett M. (1995), Realność przeszłości, przeł. T. Szubka, w: T. Szubka (red.), Metafizyka w filozofii analitycznej, Lublin: Towarzystwo Naukowe KUL, s. 257–274.
13. Dummett M. (1998), Logiczna podstawa metafizyki, przeł. W. Sady, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
14. Dummett M. (2000), Elements of Intuitionism, wyd. 2, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
15. Dummett M. (2006a), Thought and Reality, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
16. Dummett M. (2006b), Znaczenie i uzasadnienie, przeł. T. Szubka, w: U.M. Żegleń (red.), Teoria znaczenia Michaela Dummetta i jej konsekwencje metafizyczne, Toruń: Dom Wydawniczy Duet, s. 119–143.
17. Dummett M. (2007), Reply to Hilary Putnam, w: R.E. Auxier, L.E. Hahn (red.), The Philosophy of Michael Dummett, Chicago: Open Court, s. 168–184.
18. Dummett M. (2010), Natura i przyszłość filozofii, przeł. M. Iwanicki, T. Szubka, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo IFiS PAN.
19. McDowell J. (1987), In Defence of Modesty, w: B. Taylor (red.), Michael Dummett: Contributions to Philosophy, Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, s. 59–80.
20. Putnam H. (1981), Reason, Truth and History, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
21. Putnam H. (1994), Sense, Nonsense and the Senses: An Inquiry into the Powers of the Human Mind, „Journal of Philosophy” 91 (9), s. 445–517.
22. Putnam H. (1998), Wiele twarzy realizmu i inne eseje, przeł. A. Grobler, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
23. Putnam H. (2004), Ethics without Ontology, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
24. Putnam H. (2011), Argument teoriomodelowy a poszukiwanie realizmu zdroworozsądkowego, przeł. K. Czerniawski, T. Szubka, „Filozofia Nauki” 73 (1), s. 7–24.
25. Szubka T. (2001), Antyrealizm semantyczny. Studium analityczne, Lublin: Redakcja Wydawnictw KUL.
26. Szubka T. (2009), Filozofia analityczna. Koncepcje, metody, ograniczenia, Wrocław: Fundacja na Rzecz Nauki Polskiej.
27. Tennant N. (1997), The Taming of the True, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
28. Tennant N. (2009), Cognitive Phenomenology, Semantic Qualia, and Luminous Knowledge, w: P. Greenough, D. Pritchard (red.), Williamson on Knowledge, Oxford: Oxford University Press, s. 237–256.
29. Williamson T. (1996), Cognitive Homelessness, „The Journal of Philosophy” 93 (11), s. 554–573.
30. Woleński J. (2001), Epistemologia, t. III: Wiedza i poznanie, Kraków: Aureus.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Krzysztof Czerniawski
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Warszawski, Wydział Filozofii, ul. Krakowskie Przedmieście 3, 00-927 Warszawa
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

While working on the oeuvre of P.F. Strawson (1919–2006), and especially on his metaphysics, I had a unique opportunity to exchange ideas with this eminent exponent of Oxford philosophy. Those exchanges, of which some have been reflected in private correspondence and in a published reply to one of my papers, were focussed on various interpretative questions. Three threads of those discussions seem especially pertinent for grasping the gist of Strawson’s philosophy and its general orientation. The first one concerned the nature of philosophical analysis, or to be more precise, the connective model of it, favoured by Strawson, and its relationship with the idea of concept presupposition. The second thread had to do with the position taken by the Oxford philosopher in the realism debate on three levels: semantic, epistemological, and metaphysical. Strawson made every effort to take a realist stand in this debate and avoid antirealism in any of its forms; however, his realism is in many respects very moderate and not so distant from antirealism. Similarly moderate was his stand in the traditional debate about universals, constituting the topic of the third thread of the exchanges with Strawson. He claimed that universals exist, but at the same time emphasized that they are objects of pure thought alone and as such do not form a part of the spatiotemporal world in which we live. One cannot also say much about the relation of exemplification in virtue of which universals manifest themselves in the world as particular instances. Presentation and elaboration of these three threads has led to the conclusion that although Strawson was a deeply systematic thinker, he avoided wide-ranging and ambitious statements and radical views. In characteristically minimalist way he dispelled some questions, and the ultimate resolution of many crucial and fundamental issues were for him choice and taking a particular attitude or stance.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Tadeusz Szubka
ORCID: ORCID

This page uses 'cookies'. Learn more