Search results

Filters

  • Journals
  • Authors
  • Keywords
  • Date
  • Type

Search results

Number of results: 10
items per page: 25 50 75
Sort by:
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The article poses the question of how the Polish philosophy of the postwar period responded to the evil of the 20th century totalitarianism, as exemplified by atrocities committed in Kolyma and Auschwitz. The problem is analyzed by focusing on three concepts of evil developed by Polish philosophers after World War II: the realistic view (Mieczysław Krąpiec), the phenomenological‑dialogical interpretation (Józef Tischner) and the view proposed by Leszek Kołakowski. Then, the question of evil in general, and of evil at the present time, is connected to the question of the relationship between evil and conscience.
Go to article

Bibliography

Adorno T.W. (1986), Rozważania o metafizyce, w: tenże, Dialektyka negatywna, przeł. K. Krzemieniowa, Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe, s. 507–573.

Bauman Z. (2013), Nowoczesność i Zagłada, przeł. T. Kunz, Kraków: Wydawnictwo Literackie. Jan Paweł II (2005), Pamięć i tożsamość. Rozmowy na przełomie tysiącleci, Kraków: Znak.

Kłoczowski J.A. (1987), Sceptyk i mistyk, w: Obecność. Leszkowi Kołakowskiemu w 60. rocznicę urodzin, Londyn: Aneks, s. 52–67.

Kołakowski L. (1984), Czy diabeł może być zbawiony?, w: tenże, Czy diabeł może być zbawiony i 27 innych kazań, Londyn: Aneks, s. 149–157.

Kołakowski L. (1990a), Iluzje demitologizacji, w: tenże, Cywilizacja na ławie oskarżonych, Warszawa: Res Publica, s. 215–236.

Kołakowski L. (1990b), Rozmowy z diabłem, w: tenże, Bajki różne. Opowieści biblijne. Rozmowy z diabłem, Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo „Iskry”.

Kołakowski L. (1994), Obecność mitu, Wrocław: Wydawnictwo Dolnośląskie.

Kołakowski L. (2002), Kapłan i błazen (Rozważania o teologicznym dziedzictwie współczesnego myślenia), w: tenże, Pochwała niekonsekwencji. Pisma rozproszone sprzed roku 1968, t. 2, Londyn: Puls.

Kołakowski L. (2014), Jezus ośmieszony. Esej apologetyczny i sceptyczny, przeł. D. Zańko, Kraków: Znak.

Kowalczyk S. (1995), Zło – problemem czy tajemnicą, w: tenże, Podstawy światopoglądu chrześcijańskiego, Wrocław: Wydawnictwo Wrocławskiej Księgarni Archidiecezjalnej, s. 189–209.

Krasicki J. (2002a), Rozum i zło (zamiast wstępu), w: tenże, Przeciw nicości. Eseje. Kraków: Księgarnia Akademicka, s. 9–13.

Krasicki J. (2002b), Świadek Dobra, w: tenże, Przeciw nicości. Eseje, Kraków: Księgarnia Akademicka, s. 129–144.

Krasicki J. (2002c), Zło epoki, w: tenże, Przeciw nicości. Eseje, Kraków: Księgarnia Akademicka, s. 85–89.

Krasicki J. (2011), O nagim życiu, w: tenże, Po „śmierci Boga”. Eseje eschatologiczne, Kraków: Homini, s. 167–176.

Krąpiec M.A. (1995), Dlaczego zło? Rozważania filozoficzne, Lublin: Redakcja Wydawnictw KUL.

Lehman K. (1990), Tajemnica zła, przeł. L. Balter, „Communio. Międzynarodowy Przegląd Teologiczny” 3 (57), s. 22–31.

Marszałek I. (2014), Józef Tischner i filozoficzne koncepcje zła. Czy zło jest w nas, czy między nami?, Kraków: WAM.

Morawska A. (1970), Jak to się mogło stać?, „Znak” 9 (195), s. 1174–1190.

Podsiad A. (1984), Gabriel Marcel, czyli próba chrześcijańskiego egzystencjalizmu, w: G. Marcel, Homo viator, przeł. P. Lubicz, Warszawa: Instytut Wydawniczy Pax, s. 289–316.

Różewicz T. (2017), Unde malum?, w: tenże, Wybór poezji, Wrocław: Ossolineum, s. 771–773.

Skarga B. (1993), Pytać o zło, „Znak” 3 (454), s. 4–12.

Skoczyński J. (2014), Glosy i uwagi, Kraków: Księgarnia Akademicka.

Tischner J. (1970), Schyłek chrześcijaństwa tomistycznego, „Znak” 1 (187), s. 1–20.

Tischner J. (1981), Człowiek zniewolony i sprawa wolności (Hegel – Dostojewski – Descartes), „Znak” 1–2 (319–320), s. 123–142.

Tischner J. (1987), Wokół spraw wiary i rozumu, w: M. Heller, A. Michalik, J. Życiński (red.), Filozofować w kontekście nauki, Kraków: Polskie Towarzystwo Teologiczne, s. 35–45.

Tischner J. (1992), Wiara w mrocznych czasach, „Znak” 4 (443), s. 5–16.

Tischner J. (1993a), Gabriel Marcel, w: tenże, Myślenie według wartości, Kraków: Znak, s. 168–172.

Tischner J. (1993b), Tomizm bez mitologii, w: tenże, Myślenie według wartości, Kraków: Znak, s. 306–315.

Tischner J. (1994), Wobec zła (wokół „Veritatis Splendor”), „Tygodnik Powszechny” 2 (2321).

Tischner J. (1998), Filozofia dramatu, Kraków: Znak.

Tokarski J. (2016), Obecność zła. O filozofii Leszka Kołakowskiego, Kraków: Universitas. „Znak” (1993), nr 3 (454): Zło odwieczne, zło dzisiejsze (numer monograficzny).
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Jan Krasicki
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Wrocławski, Instytut Filozofii, ul. Koszarowa 3/20, 51‑149 Wrocław
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The paper discusses selected topics in moral philosophy of Professor Bogusław Wolniewicz. His overall approach is marked by intellectual independence and analytic treatment of moral issues. The theory of values that he has endorsed can be described as a moderate non-religious absolutism based on weak metaphysical principles. Although in general his normative position can be assimilated to the views of an enlightened liberal, it also clashes with that position insofar as he proclaimed the existence of ontological evil and supported legitimacy of death penalty.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Joanna Górnicka-Kalinowska
ORCID: ORCID
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The article is devoted above all to the analysis of the concept of conscience in relation to the space of public life (institutional, professional). The author of the article devotes a special place to the concept of conscience in interpretation of Jürgen Habermas and his ethics of discourse. In the first part of the article, the author points to the change it has made in the modern and contemporary sense of conscience in comparison with classical interpretations. Earlier, the power of conscience was associated with the intellect, whereas today’s conscience is associated with emotions, especially with the ability to empathize, especially the subject’s ability to empathize. Some emotions are cognitive and are related to contextual knowledge. In the second part, the author analyses the concept of the development of moral consciousness of Jürgen Habermas. This concept is based on a philosophical interpretation of the conclusions of the psychologist Lawrence Kohlberg’s experiment. In conclusion, the author writes about of the presence of the “voice” of conscience in the space of public life. Defending the value of discourse on the principles of social life, it can be based on the postulate of Habermas, or the dialogue of people with sensitive consciences.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Mariusz Wojewoda
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

In the paper I show why we should consider Stoicism as the historical source of St. Thomas’s distinction between ‘conscience’ and ‘synderesis’. I claim that the Stoic terms syntērēsis and syneidēsis became, through the ages, the Thomistic synderesis and conscientia. The Stoic syntērēsis meant ‘self-preservation’, and in all animals this ‘first instinct’ refers to the body. The man is the only creature, which, because of its ‘rational nature’, preserves not necessarily its body but rather its soul, i.e. a system of values. Such preservation of someone’s axiological integrity equals ‘salvation’, and thus assimilates Stoicism to Christianity. In the Stoic system, human values follow ‘the nature’ (or ‘the human nature’ in particular), and in Thomism, they follow ‘synderesis’, or the natural inclination toward the good. In both cases we find a natural instinct that transforms itself into a rational structure of conscience. I also argue that, thanks to the moral phenomena of ‘adaptation’ (oikeiōsis) and ‘advancement’ (teleiōsis), the Stoic ethics is not completely egocentric, but incorporates also social duties.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Łukasz Kowalik
ORCID: ORCID
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The paper’s authors undertake the reflection on the stages of the evolution of Dietrich Bonhoeffer’s views on the Church and its role as it is played in the lives of its singular members and in the context of the Reformation’s ethical heritage. One can distinguish among three stages of the Bonhoefferian ecclesiology, deepening his vision of the Church. As far as the first one is considered, the Church is defined as the spiritual community of believers, outside of which salvation is impossible. At the second stage the German theologian accentuates the sinfulness of man as a member of the Church. Its recognition constitutes the basis for the transformation that can take place in the human individual due to accepting Christ into oneself. The third stage is stepping into the world of „before-final” matters in the full responsibility for the choices made by particular members of the ecclesial community. The Church, as Bonhoeffer saw it, was supposed to support itself on strong pillars: on freedom, personal responsibility, imitating Christ, neighbourly love, on sacraments and Gospel. In this aspect Bonhoeffer was the faithful continuator of the Reformation program.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Marcin Hintz
Maria Urbańska-Bożek
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

Observing current trends in moral theology, especially in the field of bioethics, has long raised both the methodological and meritorious problem of obscuring or even removing the boundaries between good and evil. Divergence and contradiction have become a strange scientific standard in theological-moral discourse in the derivation of Hegel’s synthesis on fundamental moral questions. Depositum fidei morale, which is based on the Decalogue, Lex aeterna, and lex naturalis, seems to be giving way to post-Christian Wittgenstein language-games, in which the clear line between good and evil (including truth and falsehood), determined by the transcendent Authority of God, has been relativized. The reflection of the relationship between the norm and conscience, as well as the relationship between good and evil, in the light of the Thomistic philosophical-theological patrimony, seeks to point to the need of accepting an adequate logical re-examination of the ethical analysis of a human act. Without this, it is impossible to continue not only in Traditio, but also in finding a universal reference point for distinguishing between good and evil in the complicated world of contemporary bioethics, which responds to revolutionary biotechnologies in the field of biomedicine.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

René Balák
1

  1. Piešťany, Slovakia
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

Bogusław Wolniewicz presented his axiological system in four volumes of Filozofia i wartości (“Philosophy and Values”: 1993, 1998, 2003, 2016). For Wolniewicz, just as for his mentor Henryk Elzenberg, axiology is openly assertive and encompasses a painful confrontation of opposite moral beliefs. Wolniewicz’s vision of the reality is gloom, bitter, dramatic and deeply pessimistic. In history he detects unwelcome contributions of demonic powers (Manichaeism), he also believes that human moral character is genetically given and immutable (determinism), that some people are deprived of conscience (dualism), and that the tendency toward evil cannot be reformed (non-meliorism), human reason is not sufficient for a morally good action (voluntarism), while the so-called free will is no more than a manifestation of instincts (irrationalism). Everyone follows their pleasure (hedonism), but not everyone seeks pleasure in the same actions. In particular, some people take pleasure in cruel and destructive behaviour (demonism), while some others mind their own business (utilitarianism), and rare are those who devote themselves to higher values (perfectionism). Religion is a human invention and it emerges as a natural phenomenon in reaction to the fact of mortality. The institution of the Church should nevertheless be honored even by nonbelievers because it supports conservative values. In contemporary Western civilization a crisis can be observed between the conservative part of society (‘right-handed orientation’) and the liberal one (‘left-handed orientation’). Hateful emotions appear on both sides and are dangerous to Western unity. Conservative orientation is attached to the idea of fate, i.e. irrational power that occasionally turns human life into tragedy (fatalism). Wolniewicz’s vision is close to the theology of St. Augustine (original sin, predestination, radical dualism of good and evil) but without a consolation in hope for immortality.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Łukasz Kowalik
ORCID: ORCID
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The concept of conscience is analyzed here in two different ways: the systematic and the historical-literary. As to the first, systematic perspective, I distinguish (in part 1) three levels of conscience and on every level I identify two opposite categories (conscience that is ‛individual’ versus ‛collective’; ‛emotional’ versus ‛intellectual’; ‛motivating ex ante’ versus ‛evaluating ex post’). In the second, historical-literary perspective, I analyze two literary cases of fictional characters usually thought of as being guided or affected by conscience. The first case is the ancient Greek tragedy and here I offer (in part 2) a comment on the Sophoclean Antigone and the Euripidean Orestes presenting them both as dramas that contain an exemplary formulation of the phenomenon of conscience. Although Antigone and Orestes express their main principles of action in apparently different words, I suggest (in part 3) the two poetical visions of conscience are equally based upon a highly emotional behavior called pathos by the Greek. Thereby I provide a reason, why ancient philosophers created a new concept of conscience intended as an alternative to the poetical vision of human behavior. The new philosophical concept of conscience was based upon an axiological behavior called ethos. I also coin (in part 4) a concept of the ‛community of conscience’ where I distinguish four ‛aspects of solidarity’ in conscience, namely, somebody’s own self, a group of significant persons, a group of the same moral principles, and a sameness of life. In the end I turn (in part 5) to a historical-literary case in Joseph Conrad’s last novel The Rover (1923), which provoked a lively discussion among Polish authors and seems useful as an illustration of several levels of ‛solidarity of conscience’.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Łukasz Kowalik
ORCID: ORCID
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The normative system of Bogusław Wolniewicz (1927–2017) can be subsumed under three categories: (1) pessimism (fatalism, or ‘tychism’ in Wolniewicz’s terms), (2) moral determinism (‘non-meliorism’), (3) conservatism (‘right-hand orientation’). Ad (1) Wolniewicz was pessimistic in two ways: he believed human life to be tragic (fatalism) and was also convinced that most people are guided by bad instincts (dualism). Ad (2) Wolniewicz believed that moral character was biologically determined and immutable. But his strong position on this subject ignores the classical view of Aristotle or the Stoics for whom moral character (or conscience) was acquired by habit and shaped deliberately. Ad (3) I suggest that a good historical example of conservative tendency was Critias of Athens. His famous fragment of the Sisyphus contains the idea of a supremacy of laws over human passions, and reduces religion to a supportive role with respect to ethics and politics. Wolniewicz’s dualism of right-hand and left-hand orientation encourages me to distinguish between a right-wing and a left-wing perception of value. For a leftist, value is intensity of a chosen feature (progressive value), whereas for a rightist, value is an area of freedom between inacceptable extremities (modular value). On these premises I propose a simple model of axiological conflict between left-wing and right-wing citizens.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Łukasz Kowalik
ORCID: ORCID
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

Neuroscience deals with the issue of moral judgment. That term already has a long history in philosophical reflection. Both fields, the neurosciences and the philosophy, use different methodologies when applying it. The approach of neuroscientists tends to be reductionist. This article seeks to overcome this reductionism. The main question is: How the term “moral judgment” is understood in neurosciences? Is its understanding very different from that which is present in moral philosophy? To answer, in the first part of the article, the author investigates the meaning of the term “moral judgment” in four scientifical models: in the moral intuitionism of experimental psychology, in Social Intuitionist Model by Jonathana Haidt, in Dual-Process Theory by Joshua Green, and finaly, in Somatic Marker Hypothesis by Antonio Damasio. These reflections introduce the second part of which the subject is an examination of Christian moral philosophy and its confrontation with the findings of neuroscientists.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Szczepan Kaleciak
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Papieski Jana Pawła II w Krakowie

This page uses 'cookies'. Learn more