Search results

Filters

  • Journals
  • Keywords
  • Date
  • Type

Search results

Number of results: 14
items per page: 25 50 75
Sort by:
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

This article deals with a debate in the pages of the interwar press over a memorial landscape park opened in 1932 at Żelazowa Wola, the birthplace of Fryderyk Chopin. Designed by Franciszek Krzywda- Polkowski, the park provoked a flood of opinions and commentaries from contemporary cultural luminaries. The discussions raged mostly in literary periodicals as well as popular newspapers and magazines. The article attempts to reconstruct the narrative patterns of the debate around its two poles, represented by the admirers and opponents of Krzywda-Polkowski's innovative design.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Michał Ceglarek
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Narodowy Instytut Fryderyka Chopina, Muzeum Fryderyka Chopina, Pałac Gnińskich PL 00-368 Warszawa
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

System aksjologiczny Elzenberga od strony logiki budowany był świetnie, ale załamał się, gdyż był źle posadowiony antropologicznie. Po pierwsze, opierał się na aksjomacie Rousseau (melioryzm), głoszącym, że rozum zwraca wolę stale ku lepszemu. Ponadto zawierał aksjomat drugi – ujmujący ogólniej stosunek rozumu do woli. W postaci kanonicznej aksjomat ten brzmi: (AE) „Jeżeli wiemy, że coś powinno być, to powinniśmy też chcieć, żeby było”. Formalnie tę niby prostą i oczywistą formułę można wyrazić dwojako: (AE1) O(wx(Op) ⇒ chx(p)); (AE2) wx(Op) ⇒ O(chx(p)). (W obu wersjach poprzednik oznacza rozum, a następnik wolę.) Analiza logiczna ujawnia jednak, że wszelka oczywistość z aksjomatu Elzenberga się ulatnia. Elzenberg stawia się swoim aksjomatem w jednej z dwu wielkich tradycji zachodniej myśli etycznej: na linii Sokrates – Tomasz – Kant. To etyczny intelektualizm, któremu naprzeciw staje etyczny woluntaryzm (czy lepiej: woluntatyzm), reprezentowany przez linię Augustyn – Anzelm – Duns Szkot – Hume – Schopenhauer. Otóż intelektualizm etyczny jest poglądem fałszywym – chimerą czy iluzją. Jedyną przyczyną ludzkich działań jest osobowa wola; rozum jest bierny – na dobro i zło ślepy. Nie on dyktuje woli, co ma chcieć, tylko ona dyktuje to sobie sama, autonomicznie. „My” i „nasza wola” to jedno; a rozum stoi obok.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Bogusław Wolniewicz
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

In the article I discuss the modal version of the so‑called ‘consequence argument’ for incompatibilism. I quote and review critical remarks that predominate in the literature, and try to answer them. I show that the main strategy employed with the view to undermining the consequence argument revolves on the meanings of expressions used in it. The premises are allegedly false, the conclusion is not strong enough, and the rules are incorrect. I object to this kind of strategy and claim that the consequence argument should be assessed on its merits and declared as correct. It is a strong reason in favor of the truth of incompatibilism.
Go to article

Bibliography

Beebee H. (2013), Free Will. An Introduction, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Beebee H., Mele A. (2002), Humean Compatibilism, „Mind” 111, s. 201–223.
Campbell J.K. (2007), Free Will and the Necessity of the Past, „Analysis” 67, s. 105– 111.
Campbell J.K. (2010), Compatibilism and Fatalism: Reply to Loss, „Analysis” 70, s. 71–76.
Ginet C. (1966), Might We Have No Choice?, w: K. Lehrer (red.), Freedom and Determinism, New York: Random House, s. 87–104.
Grobler A. (2006), Metodologia nauk, Kraków: Aureus – Znak.
Huemer M. (2000), Van Inwagen’s Consequence Argument, „The Philosophical Review” 109, s. 525–544.
Kane R. (2007), Libertarianism, w: J.M. Fischer, R. Kane, D. Pereboom, M. Vargas, Four Views on Free Will, Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, s. 5–43.
Lewis D. (1979), Counterfactual Dependence and Time’s Arrow, „Nous” 13, s. 455– 476.
Lewis D. (1981), Are We Free to Break the Laws?, „Theoria” 3, s. 113–121.
McKay T.J., Johnson D. (1996), A Reconsideration of An Argument Against Compatibilism, „Philosophical Topics” 24, s. 113–122.
Speak D. (2012), The Consequence Argument Revisited, w: R. Kane (red.), The Oxford Handbook of Free Will, Oxford Handbooks Online, www.oxfordhandbooks.com.
Van Inwagen P. (1975), The Incompatibility of Free Will and Determinism, „Philosophical Studies” 27, s. 185–199.
Van Inwagen P. (1983), An Essay on Free Will, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Van Inwagen P. (2000), Free Will Remains a Mystery, „Philosophical Perspectives” 14, s. 1–19.
Vihvelin K. (2000), Libertarian Compatibilism, „Philosophical Perspectives” 14, s. 139–166.
Warfield T.A. (2000), Causal Determinism and Human Freedom are Incompatible: A New Argument for Incompatibilism, „Philosophical Perspectives” 14, s. 167–180.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Andrzej Nowakowski
1

  1. Uniwersytet Marii Curie‑Skłodowskiej w Lublinie, Wydział Filozofii i Socjologii, Pl. M. Curie‑Skłodowskiej 4, 20‑031 Lublin
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

In the submitted study, the author shows that Paul in the propositio (12,1-2) the section of encouragement (12,3-15,13), although he does not use the word syneidēsis directly, but the words used in it refer to him in conjunction with his basic functions and prove in this way how fundamental it is to renew the mind in the right, i.e. salvifically effective, education of Christian conscience. He does so in the encouragement context to make the recipients aware of how important it is to have a renewed mind and conscience in being and continuing to become a Christian in everyday and concrete living as well as practicing faith in Jesus. With propositio, he makes the foundation on which he builds the paraclesical message of the Letter. It clearly states that permanently renewed by the Gospel of God mind, is an absolute condition for an uninterrupted evangelical renewal of conscience. Thus, renewed in this way conscience is the only deity of mercy granted to sinful humanity, which guarantees constant faithfulness to its norms of judgment with God’s justice revealed in Christ, the Son of God, or his absolute righteousness, which is an indispensable condition for achieving eternal salvation.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Zdzisław Żywica
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

Artykuł przedstawia kulisy powstania tygodnika „Wola Ludu”, organu naczelnego PSL „Piast” wydawanego w Warszawie w latach 1921–1931. Założenie pisma wynikało z walk frakcyjnych wewnątrz stronnictwa między grupami Macieja Rataja, Jana Dąbskiego oraz Wincentego Witosa. Chociaż periodyk stanowił jedno z głównych pism PSL „Piast”, dotychczas nie doczekał się szczegółowych badań naukowych. W ramach pisania artykułu została przeprowadzona szeroka kwerenda źródłowa oparta głownie na pamiętnikach i wspomnie-niach działaczy ludowych, a także analiza prasoznawcza wraz z zaprezentowaniem periodyku na tle innych organów prasowych PSL „Piast”.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Mateusz Ratyński
1

  1. Muzeum Historii Polskiego Ruchu Ludowego Aleja Wilanowska 204 PL 02-765 Warszawa
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The paper tries to defend the thesis that it is impossible to decide upon moral issues without any references to the ontology of the world we live in. An illustrative example of the main argumentation line is the choice made by Cypher—a second plan character in the movie Matrix. Cypher decides to betray human rebels fighting against machines for freedom and, as a reward, accepts affluent life in the virtual reality. His choice seems to be superficially reprehensible because of the abandonment of the real world and authentic life. However, one can argue that the dichotomy between the real and virtual world is seeming. By choosing the virtual reality Cypher decided to act in a world which, like the real world, makes it possible to be a moral subject and enables authentic experience. The difference between both the worlds lies in the type of determination limiting any conscious subject. Cypher prefers to live in a world determined by the algorithm of Matrix more than in a world where his behaviour is determined by genes and other biological factors.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Jacek Gurczyński
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

Struktury architektoniczne powstają na podstawie warunków odczytywanych przez autora jako determinanty jego projektu. W przypadku Centrum Chopinowskiego i Muzeum Chopina w Żelazowej Woli, były to warunki kontekstu przyrodniczo-kulturowego, warunki konserwatorskie, funkcje. Istotne były także zmiany projektu w trakcie realizacji.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Bolesław Stelmach
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

Bogusław Wolniewicz presented his axiological system in four volumes of Filozofia i wartości (“Philosophy and Values”: 1993, 1998, 2003, 2016). For Wolniewicz, just as for his mentor Henryk Elzenberg, axiology is openly assertive and encompasses a painful confrontation of opposite moral beliefs. Wolniewicz’s vision of the reality is gloom, bitter, dramatic and deeply pessimistic. In history he detects unwelcome contributions of demonic powers (Manichaeism), he also believes that human moral character is genetically given and immutable (determinism), that some people are deprived of conscience (dualism), and that the tendency toward evil cannot be reformed (non-meliorism), human reason is not sufficient for a morally good action (voluntarism), while the so-called free will is no more than a manifestation of instincts (irrationalism). Everyone follows their pleasure (hedonism), but not everyone seeks pleasure in the same actions. In particular, some people take pleasure in cruel and destructive behaviour (demonism), while some others mind their own business (utilitarianism), and rare are those who devote themselves to higher values (perfectionism). Religion is a human invention and it emerges as a natural phenomenon in reaction to the fact of mortality. The institution of the Church should nevertheless be honored even by nonbelievers because it supports conservative values. In contemporary Western civilization a crisis can be observed between the conservative part of society (‘right-handed orientation’) and the liberal one (‘left-handed orientation’). Hateful emotions appear on both sides and are dangerous to Western unity. Conservative orientation is attached to the idea of fate, i.e. irrational power that occasionally turns human life into tragedy (fatalism). Wolniewicz’s vision is close to the theology of St. Augustine (original sin, predestination, radical dualism of good and evil) but without a consolation in hope for immortality.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Łukasz Kowalik
ORCID: ORCID
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

In the author’s opinion the traditional image of a human is incorrect: it is not the rational soul that directs people’s behaviour, but a set of programs (neural applications) recorded in the brain. The ego (sense, awareness, will) is able to block their action as long as the upbringing of the person in question has created the right habits and thus initiated proper programs in the brain. Human (as well as animals) turns out to be a combination of the matter (‘body’), spirit (‘ego’) and abstracts (neural applications). The difference between humans and animals is the complexity of human’s neural software and the ability to pursue the non-utilitarian purposes.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Jędrzej Stanisławek
ORCID: ORCID
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The article presents Peter F. Strawson’s remarks on the free will debate, which he has presented in the essay ‘Freedom and Resentment’. Strawson avoids taking a stance on the question whether the thesis of determinism is correct. Instead he shows the essential difficulties and far reaching consequences of acknowledging this thesis. He recognizes the inseparable connection between freedom and responsibility in the philosophy after Kant. He consequently questions whether we really understand what it would mean to claim that determinism is true. He focuses on what he calls ‘reactiv attitudes’ triggered by the way in which other people behave toward us. Their behavior evokes emotional reaction in us – gratitude, respect, curiosity, but also distrust, resentment, disappointment. Those emotional responses are not purely subjective and they underlie moral judgments and complicated interpersonal relations. We suspend our reactive attitudes towards animals, very small children or people that we think are mentally ill. Instead we adopt objective (psychiatric, scientific) attitudes towards them. But to acknowledge the thesis of determinism implicates that we should treat all people this way. The paper is not so much concerned with an analysis of advantages and weak points of Strawson’s version of compatibilism, but focuses instead on the originality of his contribution to the debate on free will and on his brilliant treatment of reactive attitudes.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Karolina Rychter
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

W artykule zestawiam ze sobą i zarazem oceniam dwa zupełnie odmienne sposoby ujmowania rzeczywistości moralnej. Immanuel Kant stworzył nie tylko bardzo wymagającą, ale zarazem zawiłą, sztuczną i nieempiryczną etykę. W dodatku jest ona mocno obciążona metafizycznie, a nawet teologicznie. Natomiast Peter Strawson w artykule z 1962 roku dokonał naturalistycznego i realistycznego opisu rzeczywistości moralnej.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Wacław Janikowski
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The paper summarizes the debate concerning the divine hiddenness argument. First, it presents two versions of the argument that was initially formulated by J.L. Schellenberg and subsequently discussed over the last twenty years and it marks its most important theses. Then the author indicates some possible rebuttals, segregating them according to the challenged premises. Particularly noteworthy, he argues, are these theistic answers that accuse the images of God assumed by the hiddenness argument of excessive anthropomorphism and those that try to point out higher goods justifying divine hiddenness. In conclusion the author claims that the hiddenness argument proves atheism only if by theism one understands theistic personalism. Other positions, such as ultimism or theism of transcendence, are not threatened by the argument.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Marek Dobrzeniecki
ORCID: ORCID
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

Akratic actions are usually defined as intentional actions which conflict with the agent’s best judgement. As both irrational and conscious, actions of that type stand in need of an explanation. In this paper I reconstruct and criticize Donald Davidson’s classical standpoint on the problem of akrasia. I show the disadvantages of Davidsonian conception of practical reasoning and I defend the conception of syllogistic reasoning. I also criticize the theory of intention as unconditional normative judgement. Against Davidson’s view, I argue for the theory of intention as an act of will (not a judgement). According to this theory of intention and practical reasoning, akratic actions should be explained as actions caused by an act of will which conflicts with the best judgement. I propose to interpret the inclination of will to conflict or to follow the best judgement by the theory of habitus.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Agata Machcewicz-Grad
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

Henryk Elzenberg zajmował się aksjologią merytoryczną i aksjologią formalną. Można wyróżnić względnie wyraźne okresy tej działalności. Aksjologia merytoryczna przypadła głównie na okres od około 1910 do 1931 r. Do roku 1930 Elzenberg opracowywał różne szczegółowe zagadnienia, potem w latach 1930–1931 analizy jego koncentrowały się m.in. na podsumowaniu szczegółowej aksjologii merytorycznej. Aksjologię formalną Elzenberg rozwijał od 1930 r. do maja 1940 r. W okresie późniejszym zaczął wątpić w swoje wcześniejsze ustalenia. Ten okres wątpienia trwał od maja 1940 do około grudnia 1943 r.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Jan Zubelewicz

This page uses 'cookies'. Learn more