Search results

Filters

  • Journals
  • Authors
  • Keywords
  • Date
  • Type

Search results

Number of results: 4
items per page: 25 50 75
Sort by:
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

According to Descartes, it is possible to doubt successfully that there is external world, all around us, yet still to have language, in place, without any complication. According to Wittgenstein, to doubt everything about the external world except language means nothing more than to doubt everything about the external world including language. Why? No speaker is more certain about the meaning of his words than about the external things he believes to be unassailable (for example, that he has two hands and two legs). Without this constitutive connection there would be no communication of a definite sense. Wittgenstein suggests that, after the author of the Meditations on First Philosophy adopts the hypothesis of evil deceiver, we are only under the impression that we deal with language (or that we read a text). We instead deal with symptoms of something rather different. The objective of this paper is to critically reassess Wittgenstein’s criticism of the possibility of holding such a radical sceptical position.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Tomáš Čanal
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The embryonic architecture, which draws inspiration from the biological process of ontogeny, has built-in mechanisms for self-repair. The entire genome is stored in the embryonic cells, allowing the data to be replicated in healthy cells in the event of a single cell failure in the embryonic fabric. A specially designed genetic algorithm (GA) is used to evolve the configuration information for embryonic cells. Any failed embryonic cell must be indicated via the proposed Built-in Selftest (BIST) the module of the embryonic fabric. This paper recommends an effective centralized BIST design for a novel embryonic fabric. Every embryonic cell is scanned by the proposed BIST in case the self-test mode is activated. The centralized BIST design uses less hardware than if it were integrated into each embryonic cell. To reduce the size of the data, the genome or configuration data of each embryonic cell is decoded using Cartesian Genetic Programming (CGP). The GA is tested for the 1-bit adder and 2-bit comparator circuits that are implemented in the embryonic cell. Fault detection is possible at every function of the cell due to the BIST module’s design. The CGP format can also offer gate-level fault detection. Customized GA and BIST are combined with the novel embryonic architecture. In the embryonic cell, self-repair is accomplished via data scrubbing for transient errors.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Gayatri Malhotra
1 2
Punithavathi Duraiswamy
2
J.K. Kishore
1

  1. U R Rao Satellite Centre, India
  2. M S Ramaiah University of Applied Science, India
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

Antirealism is often regarded by philosophers as a model example of contemporary anti‑Cartesianism, chiefly because of the argumentation by Hilary Putnam presented in his Brains in a Vat and deeply rooted in antirealist semantics. But if we look closer, relations between Cartesianism and antirealism cannot be reduced to an opposition but are much more complex. Like Cartesianism, antirealism also attaches great significance to methodology universal for all philosophy, although antirealist ‘philosophy of thought’, contrary to its Cartesian counterpart, is antipsychological and boils down to Wittgensteinian philosophy that interprets language as something inherently public. But Dummettian antirealism contains also a Fregean concept of systematic theory of meaning, which should provide clear view of language rules and give us an ability to correct our imperfect language practice. For Wittgenstein and Putnam, who view this practice as the essence of language, this kind of attempt to correct language from outside is unacceptable. In this matter, Michael Dummett seems to be rather in harmony with the Cartesian ideal of thought as pure and distinct, and with the program of detached rationality. This impression is strengthened by his demand to adopt a ‘full‑blooded’ theory of meaning. Moreover, as it has been noted by Timothy Williamson, antirealism demands luminosity of meaning, which makes you wonder if it is not, like Cartesianism, one more case of epistemological foundationalism. These problems of antirealism seem to suggest strong internal tensions arising from an attempt, not entirely successful, to unify the thought of later Wittgenstein with more traditional rationalisms of Descartes and Frege.
Go to article

Bibliography

1. Ambrus V. (1999), Is Putnam’s Causal Theory of Meaning Compatible with Internal Realism?, „Journal for General Philosophy of Science” 30, s. 1–16.
2. Candlish S., Wrisley G. (2019), Private Language, w: E.N. Zalta (red.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall Edition), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/ fall2019/entries/private‑language/
3. Czerniawski K. (2010), Argument teoriomodelowy trzydzieści lat później, „Filozofia Nauki” 71 (3), s. 19–41.
4. Czerniawski K. (2014), Trzy wersje epistemicznej teorii prawdy: Dummett, Putnam, Wright, Warszawa: Ośrodek Badań Filozoficznych.
5. Diamond C. (1991), The Realistic Spirit: Wittgenstein, Philosophy, and the Mind, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
6. Dummett M. (1973), Frege: Philosophy of Language, New York: Harper & Row.
7. Dummett M. (1978), Truth and Other Enigmas, London: Duckworth.
8. Dummett M. (1987a), Reply to John McDowell, w: B. Taylor (red.), Michael Dummett: Contributions to Philosophy, Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, s. 253–268.
9. Dummett M. (1987b), Reply to Neil Tennant, w: B. Taylor (red.), Michael Dummett: Contributions to Philosophy, Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, s. 235–252.
10. Dummett M. (1993a), The Seas of Language, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
11. Dummett M. (1993b), Origins of Analytical Philosophy, London: Duckworth.
12. Dummett M. (1995), Realność przeszłości, przeł. T. Szubka, w: T. Szubka (red.), Metafizyka w filozofii analitycznej, Lublin: Towarzystwo Naukowe KUL, s. 257–274.
13. Dummett M. (1998), Logiczna podstawa metafizyki, przeł. W. Sady, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
14. Dummett M. (2000), Elements of Intuitionism, wyd. 2, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
15. Dummett M. (2006a), Thought and Reality, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
16. Dummett M. (2006b), Znaczenie i uzasadnienie, przeł. T. Szubka, w: U.M. Żegleń (red.), Teoria znaczenia Michaela Dummetta i jej konsekwencje metafizyczne, Toruń: Dom Wydawniczy Duet, s. 119–143.
17. Dummett M. (2007), Reply to Hilary Putnam, w: R.E. Auxier, L.E. Hahn (red.), The Philosophy of Michael Dummett, Chicago: Open Court, s. 168–184.
18. Dummett M. (2010), Natura i przyszłość filozofii, przeł. M. Iwanicki, T. Szubka, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo IFiS PAN.
19. McDowell J. (1987), In Defence of Modesty, w: B. Taylor (red.), Michael Dummett: Contributions to Philosophy, Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, s. 59–80.
20. Putnam H. (1981), Reason, Truth and History, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
21. Putnam H. (1994), Sense, Nonsense and the Senses: An Inquiry into the Powers of the Human Mind, „Journal of Philosophy” 91 (9), s. 445–517.
22. Putnam H. (1998), Wiele twarzy realizmu i inne eseje, przeł. A. Grobler, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Naukowe PWN.
23. Putnam H. (2004), Ethics without Ontology, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
24. Putnam H. (2011), Argument teoriomodelowy a poszukiwanie realizmu zdroworozsądkowego, przeł. K. Czerniawski, T. Szubka, „Filozofia Nauki” 73 (1), s. 7–24.
25. Szubka T. (2001), Antyrealizm semantyczny. Studium analityczne, Lublin: Redakcja Wydawnictw KUL.
26. Szubka T. (2009), Filozofia analityczna. Koncepcje, metody, ograniczenia, Wrocław: Fundacja na Rzecz Nauki Polskiej.
27. Tennant N. (1997), The Taming of the True, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
28. Tennant N. (2009), Cognitive Phenomenology, Semantic Qualia, and Luminous Knowledge, w: P. Greenough, D. Pritchard (red.), Williamson on Knowledge, Oxford: Oxford University Press, s. 237–256.
29. Williamson T. (1996), Cognitive Homelessness, „The Journal of Philosophy” 93 (11), s. 554–573.
30. Woleński J. (2001), Epistemologia, t. III: Wiedza i poznanie, Kraków: Aureus.

Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Krzysztof Czerniawski
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Warszawski, Wydział Filozofii, ul. Krakowskie Przedmieście 3, 00-927 Warszawa
Download PDF Download RIS Download Bibtex

Abstract

The goal of this article is to show the interdependence of the reception of Don Quixote and the concept of identity. The argument is founded on the rejection of Don Quixote perceived as an invented character from the world of fiction and treating him instead as a Cartesian subject, in possession of the cogito faculty and defined by the truth. The Cartesian project, though, comes under pressure when the cogito constitutes itself by telling a story about itself. Cartesianism, a philosophy of consciousness, contains an embryo of a new reflection about subjectivity. With the new approach comes a positive reappraisal of the figure of Don Quixote and an acknowledgement of the key role of fiction in the process of becoming human. The liberation of identity from the tyranny of substantialism and the foundation of the subject on action has paved the way for treating the goals of action as originals produced by the subject rather than copies or reproductions.
Go to article

Authors and Affiliations

Iwona Krupecka
1
ORCID: ORCID

  1. Uniwersytet Gdański

This page uses 'cookies'. Learn more